|
The Spectral Ontology and Miraculous Materialism
Kimberly DeFazio
1.
In the broadest terms, materialism, as Engels puts it, "insist[s] on
explaining the world from the world itself" (Dialectics of Nature 7). It is, to put it differently, the
unyielding opponent of the otherworldly—of those projects that derive
the material world from another world of spirit or that see in the
natural world a super-natural force or design. In its most revolutionary
tendency in the modern era, materialism is determination by the mode of
production. This historical materialism is the antagonist of existing
class arrangements because, by revealing the transformative agency of
human labor in making history and producing the material world—the
social totality—it also reveals the dialectical nature of existing
social relations of private property, which inevitably come into
conflict with the revolutionary advance of the forces of production. The
more the powers of collective labor become effectively organized and
efficient at producing the means to meet the material and cultural needs
of humanity as a whole, the more intolerable becomes the restrictions
placed on this process by the needs of a few to personally profit from
it at the expense of the vast majority whose labor produces the wealth. Materialism is therefore a weapon in the historic struggle
against private property because it allows people to take part as
conscious participants in transforming relations of private ownership,
the root of social inequalities. It is for this reason that ontology—the
account of the objective constitution of reality, both natural and
social—has been central to the project of materialism, for it provides
positive knowledge of the objective world as a totality.
Since capitalism's victory in the early modern era over the feudal order
(against which the bourgeoisie deployed materialism to challenge the
spiritualizations that justified aristocratic rule), bourgeois theorists
have waged a protracted war against materialism and ontology in their
efforts to naturalize their own class interests and obscure the source
of profit in surplus value, which is what maintains class inequality
despite bourgeois democracy (equal rights). In place of materialism and
the positive knowledge of the world, they have substituted various
species of spiritualism that invert the relation of the material and the
immaterial, establishing the otherworldly as the basis of reality and,
in effect, placing it beyond the reach of human knowledge and
transformation. The attack against materialism, in other words, is where
the war against socialism—the new world governed by the principle, "From
each according to his ability, to each according to his needs!"
(Marx Critique of the Gotha Programme
531)—is fought at the
level of philosophy.
But today, as the class struggle intensifies under the global
contradictions of capital, the fight against materialism increasingly
takes place within the very terms of "materialism."
The avid intensity with which materialism is today being appropriated and
turned on its head is perhaps nowhere more evident than in Diana Coole
and Samantha Frost's collection New Materialisms: Ontology, Agency, and Politics,
which has become a new manifesto for cultural theory. Claiming that "the
radicalism of the dominant discourses which have flourished under the
cultural turn is now more or less exhausted," Coole and Frost insist
that the time has come for the return to materialism and the world of
matter (3), made possible they suggest by diverse developments in
digital technology, the natural sciences, biotechnology, the
environment, the economy, health, and climate, for instance.
The "new materialism" energetically deploys such concepts as matter,
materiality, objectivity, empirical reality, and ontology; denounces
theological explanations of the world; and declares that it is no longer
possible to ignore the way in which, as Coole and Frost put it, humans
are "embedded in a material world" (34). Yet, what is being termed materialism in the "new
materialism" is largely a physicalist notion of matter (an
experientialism which it justifies by allying itself
with the discourses of natural
science and phenomenology) and which is ideologically valuable
precisely because it is "a
materialism which excludes the historical process" (Marx
Capital Vol. 1 494). As in
eighteenth century views of the material as a passive and inert
substance that "resists" conceptuality, it is a materialism that cannot
explain the material world as a dialectical process whose motion may be
positively and reliably understood.
At the same time, the new post-historical
materialism is elaborated through a ("new") posthumanist ontological
framework that seems to offer an understanding of the social as a
totality, emphasizing interlocking "webs" of connections between the
social and natural world, and the "vital," corporeal "embeddedness" of
the human in the nonhuman. That is to say, it offers a notion of
"collective life as a complex relational field that emerges in an
intercorporeal, intersubjective 'between'" (Dianna Coole 113), in which
"phenomena are caught in a multitude of interlocking systems and forces"
(Coole and Frost 9).
Such allusions to totality of course have great
appeal at a time when the global interconnections of social and natural
life can no longer be avoided and when people struggle to understand the
conditions to which their lives are ruthlessly subjected. But what is
being offered by posthumanist ontology is in fact a
theory blocking class understanding of issues in their material
totality. It is a theory of "ecology" that empties the social out of the
world, reducing it to physical and biological dynamics of local systems.
Embeddedness and corporeality are ideological terms: their role is to
limit knowledge to local knowledge and especially to the knowledge of
experience. They are code words for anti-totality. It is not surprising,
then, that the affirmation of individual experience and rejection of
objectivity leads the new materialists to embrace spiritualism, the
framework of which is rooted in individual beliefs and feelings.
For all its criticisms of religion and metaphysics, in the end "objective
existence" according to proponents of new materialism is "only possible
because of a certain spectrality" (Cheah 77). In fact, Coole and Frost
joyfully affirm the new materialism because its "postdualism" means that
there can be "no definitive break between . . . material and spiritual
phenomena" (10). Posthumanist ontology, in other words, turns out to be
a very familiar spectral ontology—an idealism. Under the guise of a
militant anti-theological return to the material world (which is needed
to distinguish new materialism from the Right's crude defense of
theocracy), the new materialists advocate a subtle "new" reading of the
(spiritual) "life" of matter. It returns to "materialist traditions
developed prior to modernity" (Coole and Frost 4) to avoid the worldly
determination of reality and instead find "fresh applications" (4) of
spiritualism. The new materialism, consequently, is not a rejection but
an updating of the culturalism that has played an integral role in
dismantling the materialist critique of capitalism in the postwar era.
In analyzing some of the central assumptions of
"the new materialism" and its historical context, I take as my focus in
this essay Coole and Frost's anthology,
paying particular attention to the way posthumanist "ontology" and
"matter" are theorized in the book's Introduction and the section on
"The Force of Materiality," with essays by Jane Bennett, Pheng Cheah,
Samantha Frost, and Melissa A. Orlie. Their theorizations of matter and
the relation between subject and object, I argue, reflect a deep
confusion about, if not a deliberate rewriting of, some of the
"fundamental questions" of materialism and thus have profoundly
problematic implications for materialism and the struggle for a world
organized on the basis of meeting social needs. Although the book's
contributors "pluralize" materialisms (4), the resulting eclectic
bringing together of many (contradictory) arguments and traditions
nevertheless articulates a new (ideo)logic for the era of global
austerity.
2.
First, in what ways do
the new materialists distinguish themselves from existing theoretical
traditions? On the one hand, as I mentioned, proponents of the new
materialism express frustration with what Coole and Frost refer to as
the "allergy to 'the real'" of earlier textual approaches that has had
the effect of discouraging "critical inquirers from the more empirical
investigation that material processes and structures require" (6).
Taking their cue, therefore, not from the languages of textuality but
(following such theorists as Deleuze and Guatari, Bruno Latour and N.
Katherine Hayles) from the discourses of the "new" biology (i.e.,
biogenetics) and the new physics (chaos and systems theories), and often
hybridizing them with the (old) phenomenology and vitalism, the new
materialists highlight the dynamics of matter at the cellular,
molecular, subatomic, and cosmic levels and the way they subtend social
relations and constitute the human body. Indeed, they suggest that
social relations are best understood on the basis of these
physical/biological levels of "matter." "Our existence," Coole and Frost
observe,
depends from one moment to the next on myriad micro-organisms and
diverse higher species, on our own hazily understood bodily and cellular
reactions and on pitiless cosmic motions, on the material artifacts and
natural stuff that populate our environment, as well as on socioeconomic
structures that produces and reproduce the conditions of our everyday
lives. (1)
They thus ask with great urgency, "How could we ignore the power of matter and the ways it
materializes in our ordinary experiences or fail to acknowledge the
primacy of matter in our theories?" (1). For new materialists, the
problem with the "cultural turn" is in part the "constructivist
orientation" (4) of its theory, which treats matter as a social
construction with no existence or agency independent of humans. I leave
aside for now that this reading of "culturalism" is itself a culturalist
reading of the cultural turn that obscures its material basis and allows
new materialism to construct itself as different; in actually the basis
of culturalism is the treatment of ideas and practices as isolated from
the material relations of history—an ideological approach that has been
and remains the cultural common sense in global capitalism because it
deflects attention from the roots of culture in relations of
exploitation.
"Constructivist"
accounts of matter, new materialist critics argue, are no longer capable
of addressing new realities like global climate change, ecological
crisis, and growing economic disparities worldwide, not to mention the
way new technologies and new scientific discoveries have meant that
"unprecedented things are currently being done with and to matter,
nature, life, production, and reproduction" through, for instance,
biogenetics (4). They suggest that it is now necessary to address the
ways in which the material world—the world not just of objects, nature,
and the human body, but such phenomena as "the electricity grid, food,
and trash" (9)—has an "agency" which has hitherto not been accounted
for.
On the other hand, the
new materialists "share a common foe in mechanistic or deterministic
materialism" (Bennett, "A Vitalist Stopover on the Way to a New Materialism" 48). That is, the
"new" materialism differs from classical theories of materialism, since
the latter, following Newton, treated nature and matter as set in motion
by a divine (external) source. In these mechanical theories of nature,
matter's movement does not originate from within but from without and
with a clocklike precision that can be observed and measured. Moreover,
the Cartesian distinction between subject/object informing mechanical
materialisms posits an active human subject capable of knowing/mastering
a passive, natural world—a distinction that is increasingly viewed as
unethical not to mention regularly subverted by new realities, such as
growing frequencies of natural disasters which appear to exceed our
ability to understand them. It is on this basis that the new
materialists also oppose historical materialism. Historical materialism,
the new materialists claim, is equally mechanical since it treats the
agency of matter as an effect of its relation to the human subject of
labor, and is "deterministic" because it assumes causal relations in the
world exist and can be understood—an approach new materialists suggest
does not account for matter's autonomous contingency and is incapable of
addressing today's increasingly "unpredictable" realities which defy
"totality." This is the case not only in the new materialist
refurbishments of Derridean textualism, namely Cheah's rejection of the
dialectical materialist theory of totality as a "metaphysics of
presence" (72) on the basis of which he reads Marxism as "an organismic
vitalism" (87); it is also true among the new materialists claiming to
defend historical materialism, as is made clear in Jason Edward's
suggestion that we can use the Marxist notion of totality provided we
re-understand it (after Althusser and Derrida) as "a totality without a
center" (286). Which is to say, as an open field of networks in which
class is undecidable and indeterminate. This is another way of saying
that totality is only advocated by new materialists to the extent that
it is turned into a concept without any explanatory power. Consequently,
while they return to matters of political economy, the new materialists
treat historical materialism's approach to the relation of culture and
economics as "dogmatic" and opt instead for an understanding of "the
material details of everyday life and broader geopolitical and
socioeconomic structures" as a "complex, pluralistic, and relatively
open process" (Coole and Frost 7).
Whether they are defending the "immanent generativity" of matter in terms
of the new biology (Bennett, Coole and Frost), phenomenology (Frost),
deconstructive-Deleuzianism (Cheah) or Nietschean will/drives (Orlie),
the writers position themselves in the materialist tradition by more or
less explicitly appealing to the discourses of the natural sciences and
treating matter's vitality as having an existence and agency independent
of the consciousness of the subject or any divine cause, and thus
rejecting those "mysticisms derived from animism, religion, or
romanticism" (Coole, "The Inertia of Matter and the Generativity of
Flesh" 92). They oppose themselves to the more overt
religious imaginaries in which "the cosmos [i]s a rank-ordered creation,
at the top of which the Designer has placed his most vital creature,
man" (Bennett, "A Vitalist Stopover" 60), while they reject
"deterministic" (or what they also call "economistic") materialism. The new materialists, therefore, are aligned not with the Marxist
tradition of materialism, but the early modern materialists like
Spinoza, vitalists like Bergson, and phenomenologists like Husserl and
Merleau-Ponty, not to mention revealing a strong affinity for
Nietzsche—whose critique of rationality and science undergirds the
entire "new materialist" framework.
To what extent, then, is
this new defense of materialism and matter a ruthless criticism of the
earlier cultural theory it claims to move beyond? To what extent does
the new materialism represent a
return "to the most fundamental questions about the
nature of matter" (3), and to what extent are these fundamental
questions displaced? Because its emphasis on "discontinuity" and
"indeterminacy" serve to (mis)represent new materialism as "new," in
order to begin to answer such questions it will perhaps be useful to
note briefly some of the recent theoretical history of contemporary
cultural theory before examining the way in which the new materialists
understand the relation of the subject to matter and the implications
for ontology.
3.
Even prior to the contemporary "material turn," the attack on materialism
in the post-war era had to undertake the re-writing of materialism's
central concepts, hollowing them out of any connection to the material
world of labor. This made "materialism" safe while allowing material
contradictions resulting from increased exploitation to develop without
any radical challenge from the left. The speculative theory dominated by
poststructuralism since the 1960s—post-al theory—emptied the
philosophical basis of materialism in part through its critique of
essence and identity, which, as Derrida contends, are always "in advance
contaminated, that is, preoccupied, inhabited, haunted by [their] other"
(Specters of Marx
201), rendering any category—such as capital or labor or the mode
of production—continually riven by its opposite and thus subject to an
endless chain of significations that can only be arrested by a violent
epistemological closure. This is a point emphasized in Pheng Cheah'
essay, "Non-Dialectical Materialism" in New Materialisms. In arguing
for a materiality of the text, Cheah draws upon Derrida's argument that
the project of deconstruction can be understood as "materialist" only to
the extent that "matter"—normally equated with logocentric notions of
"presence," "thing" and "reality"—is re-understood as "radical alterity"
(Positions 64) which treats matter as "the figure of the text in
general" insofar as presence "becomes part of a limitless weave of
forces or an endless process or movement of referral" that is "arrested"
by metaphysical concepts like presence (Cheah 72-3). Presence is always
undermined by a lack (absence), and vice versa, rendering such concepts
epistemologically unreliable. Such a critique inevitably led to the
deconstruction of appeals to empirical reality, and especially to any
appeals to a correspondence between language and empirical reality,
which was dismissed as a totalizing will to presence (Derrida Grammatology 50), and which has been extraordinarily effective in
undermining the theoretical basis of understanding the fundamentally
exploitative relation between labor and capital (a binary which, after
Derrida, is systematically equated with presentism and shown to
deconstruct itself).
Far from a determining basis of reality, then, the material world
becomes—on the basis of such rewritings—a concept shot through with
difference (radical alterity), in effect dismantling the
("metaphysical") distinctions between presence/absence,
material/spiritual, cause/effect, etc.,
on which materialism depends.
In the post-war period, "matter"—that which has an objective
existence independent of consciousness—soon came to signify, for
instance, the "matter" of textuality (with Derrida and Barthes), the
body or the opacity of corporeality (with Butler), and (with the later
cultural turn) discourse, which unlike "textuality," refers to a
speaking subject, i.e., a subject with a body.
On these terms, if discourse is material there can be no final
(authoritative) meaning, such as the "reason" that is taken to be the
essence of the subject in the Enlightenment theory of knowledge. Along
similar lines, the very question of ontology was denounced as a
logocentric will to power and "being" itself was increasingly subject to
erasure, following the continental philosophy of the early twentieth
century—for instance, phenomenology and existentialism—which bracketed
the existence of the objective world on the grounds that it could only
be known at the level of its effects on the senses in any case.
In fact, after Derrida, ontology—the "ontology of presence as actual
reality and as objectivity"—becomes "hauntology." As Derrida explains,
"it is necessary to introduce haunting into the very construction of a
concept. Of every concept, beginning with the concepts of being and
time. That is what we would be calling here a hauntology" (Specters
of Marx 202). On these terms, any effort "to deploy the possibility
of dissipating the phantom. . . of bringing this representation back to
the world of labour, production, and exchange, so as to reduce it to its
conditions," as Marx does in his analysis of the congealed labor hidden
in the commodity form, is itself "a conjuration" that ignores the
phantom status of objectivity (Specters
of Marx 214). Even the culturalism that developed in distinction
from textual materialism and that sought to address the more "concrete"
practices of "culture" nevertheless took these deconstructive hauntings
of essence and identity as their starting point, and, following Derrida,
avoided at all costs "bringing back" representation to "the world of
labour" and "its conditions," and substituted for it a cultural
materialism that focused on the experiential particularities and
excessive contingencies of culture as themselves constitutive of
reality. Culturalism essentially reduced ontology to non-totalizable
"bits" (Gary Hall Culture in Bits).
In the wake of global economic crises of the 21st century,
however, even these rewritings of the material are losing their
effectiveness. This is made clear in Coole and Frost's comments
mentioned above about the limits of the cultural turn (and these comments of course
follow a long line of challenges within the last decade, especially by
the "new communists," Badiou, Žižek, Hardt and Negri, et. al.).
Today textualism is largely viewed as bankrupt—its emphasis on language found to be too determining
and its celebration of free play now revealed as too close to the
anti-state mantras of neoliberalism—and culturalism more broadly is seen
as having ignored the economic relations that everywhere are erupting
through cultural surfaces. It is in this context of shifting common
sense that, for instance, Mitt Romney's statement during his 2012
presidential campaign that the economic inequality between Israel and
Palestine is the effect of "cultural differences" was widely mocked, and
that the anti-Muslim hysteria of the New Atheists generated strong
opposition from the new Atheist+ movement which engages cultural
differences as relations of inequality. Social theory requires a new
basis upon which to spiritualize—with a green aroma—the increasingly
evident interconnections and contradictions of the global world. It
requires a planetary pantheism. It has found a new theoretical basis in
the "posthuman orientation" to ontology (Coole and Frost 7) that is at
the center of the new materialism and many other new theoretical trends,
such as animal studies, biopolitics, the "spectral turn," and
object-oriented philosophy. Yet, as I have begun to suggest, all of the
favorite tropes of deconstruction ("undecidability," "indeterminacy,"
"unpredictability," opposition to the "dogma" of "determination" and
"economism") remain firmly entrenched in the new materialist approach to
ontology (hence Cheah's poststructuralist essay is prominently placed in
the collection), which it has hybridized with the new terminological
"currency" of various scientific discourses.
4.
According to theorists like Bennett, Coole, Frost, and Cheah, changes in
the understanding of the material world—which they isolate from the
social relations of production and attribute to technological and
scientific advances (e.g., biogenetics, teletechnologies, nanotech)—have
put in crisis traditional
humanist values and with them the humanist model of subjectivity. The
new materialists emphasize that the humanist subject informing the
classical science of Descartes and Newton posits a false essential
(ontological) difference between the subject and the object that
situates the human subject as an active agent in relation to its object.
This object is assumed to be fundamentally distinct from (rather than
"entangled with") the subject, and capable of being known and controlled
by the subject. According to posthumanist theory, on the basis of its
ontological dualism humanism assumes the possibility of developing
objective knowledge of the external world, and, moreover, sees the world
of nature as there for humanity's taking, without regard for the
environmental consequences.
Elaborating on these subject-object relations in her essay "The Inertia
of Matter and the Generativity of Flesh," Diana Coole writes that the classical view of matter sees it as "inert" and "essentially passive
stuff, set in motion by human agents who use it as a means of survival,
modify it as a vehicle of aesthetic expression, and impose subjective
meanings upon it"; matter relative to the subject is thus "devoid of
agency" (92) in the humanist model.
Repeating the cultural turn's dogma that the most important battles
should be fought not against the material relations of exploitation but
theoretical "essentialism," Coole's argument suggests that any ontology
that posits a difference between subject and object, human and nonhuman,
is a deeply "unethical" approach to the world. Such new developments as
biogenetics, along with other scientific discoveries and technologies,
have thrown the traditional humanist subject even further into crisis.
The "crisis of the subject," new
materialists suggest, is a daily reality and not just a textual
decentering. They claim it is no longer possible to ignore the way in
which humans are "embedded in a material world" in which our actions
have (un/intended) and often destructive consequences for the bio and
eco spheres, not just the human sphere. Andrew Poe speaks to the new
posthumanist theoretical consensus when he writes,
"The subject, it seems, has come to care too much for itself,"
and he refers to this subject-focus as an "exceptionalism" that denies
objects agency (153, 154).
Just as troubling for posthumanist theorists is that the classical
(Cartesian, Newtonian) model of subjectivity presumes that it can obtain
reliable knowledge, allowing the subject to predict how matter will
operate under certain (future) circumstances; it conceives matter as
"subject to predictable causal forces" (Coole and Frost 9). Causal
forces that allow people to reliably understand the workings of the
natural and social world are assumed to be falsely and unethically
imposed on the world by the human subject;
whereas "contingency" and randomness—what Cheah refers to the
"absolute chance" (83) that is at the core of material existence—are
somehow assumed to speak the authentic (e.g., non-imposed, nonmediated)
language of being. Because "there is no longer a quantitative
relationship between cause and effect," in the words of Coole and Frost
(14), the new materialists affirm the "aleatory" nature of all reality
(14) by celebrating the "contingent, disparate capacities to structure
that emerge haphazardly through corporeal practices" (Coole 102) and
rejoice in "the element of unpredictability and indeterminacy in
action" (Bennett, "A Vitalist Stopover" 61).
I will address new materialism's theory of "matter" in more detail below.
Here, I want to point out that the new posthumanist ontological
reorientation treats the crisis of the subject as primarily a crisis of
(cultural) values, which are seen as no longer capable of responding to
new realities. Theorists, in this context, regularly marshal as evidence
"events" which reveal the human subject to be not so much in control of
the world as controlled by it:
a subjected subject whose intention is often subverted by the
material world—a subject always already at the mercy of "the mismatch
between actions, intentions, and consequences" (New
Materialisms 16). Or, in the words of Jane Bennett, whose essay in
New Materialisms is developed
out of her influential book
Vibrant Matter (which I therefore also address here), great
attention is given to "the capacity of things…to impede or block the
will and designs of humans" because these things "act as quasi agents or
forces with trajectories, propensities, or tendencies of their own" (Vibrant Matter viii). What Bennett calls "thing-power" ("A Vitalist Stopover" 48) closely echoes cultural theory's catastrophe fetish, fed by
glorifying ever-more spectacular evidence of the human subject's failure
to know the world. Following Nietzsche, rational human agency is taken to be one of
the most "mendacious" narratives of history ("On Truth" 42). Indeed, the
subject's claim to know is dismissed in posthumanist theory as the
effect of a broader field of human "fantasies" (Orlie 120). Of course,
what therefore quickly emerges from the "postdualist" ontology is less a
hybrid ontology than a reversal that privileges the object as a reified
"thing" that mystically eludes understanding. (And at that point it is
easy enough to deify the thing as an "other" that "resists" knowing in
order to appear "ethical" [cf. Ahmed 254]).
But what posthumanist theorists call the crisis of the subject is itself
rooted in material relations—which remain in the background of analysis
of even the most ardent enthusiasts of "new materialism." The humanist
subject is increasingly seen as outdated not because its
human-centeredness is now seen as unethical or even because of new
technologies. The new technologies (including biotech and
nanotechnologies) and the new approach to ethics are themselves driven
by changes in production.
What is obscured by new materialism is the structural crisis reached by
capital—due to the falling rate of profit—which has meant, especially in
the last decade, a new round of attacks on labor in the effort to
increase profits on the one hand and, on the other, the
hoarding, on the part of capitalists,
of trillions of dollars in capital rather than risk "unprofitable"
investment. Any and all previously public programs and resources—from
education and health care to water—are rapidly being privatized, at the
same time wages are being cut and any remaining unions and worker
protections are being eliminated, in a flagrant theft of surplus value.
These relations (and not simply "matter" as such) have made everyday
life precarious and unpredictable. This is especially the case with
health care in the US. The new posthumanist ontology claims to establish
an entirely new hybrid notion of the human subject as thoroughly
"embedded" in the world and thus unable to know the world in any
reliable way. But far from resisting "instrumentalized" approaches to
the world, it is itself an instrument of capitalist ideology. The new
posthumanist subject has become necessary to naturalize the increasingly
unpredictable, crisis-ridden world of global capital. The culture wars
over the pets of the 2012 presidential candidates (Romney's Irish setter
and Obama's Portuguese Water dog) are telling in this regard. Why these
candidates' dogs are made to matter is because they are taken in the
popular culture to be signs of the ethical character of their owners
(Romney is a monster for tying his Irish setter Seamus' cage to the top
of his car and Obama's Portuguese Water dog Bo is "read" in racist
ways). And yet the assumption here is that the condition of the workers
will somehow be improved if they have "good" bosses who "care" about all
creatures and respect the dignity of the weak and unfortunate. As
always, ethics deflects attention from underlying causes.
The relations of wage labor today mean not only that working people
increasingly struggle to survive while a tiny few own virtually all
social and natural resources, but that the material world that is a
product of social labor is increasingly an alien world, beyond the
producers' control. Under these
relations of commodity production, "the commodity reflects the social
characteristics of men's own labour as objective characteristics of the
products of labour themselves, as the socio-natural properties of these
things" (Marx Capital vol. 1 164-5). The new materialists do not
just take the surface of commodity life for granted, they glorify a commodified vision of the material world in which the subject is forever
alienated from her labor and learns to embrace this powerlessness
relative to the world. This is another way of saying that the
increasingly popular theoretical framework within which objects as
objects are given a new autonomy and agency independent of their
producers, and the (human) subject is itself reduced to the matter of
corporeality whose agency is neither based on labor nor rational
thinking but the microdynamics and "creative contingency" (Coole and
Frost 20) of its biological nature—is the epitome of commodity
fetishism. In fact, many of the new materialist writings read as bad
parodies of Marx's first chapter of Capital. They glorify the
material conditions under which "Their own movement within society has
for them [workers] the form of a movement made by things, and these
things, far from being under their control, in fact control them"
(167-8). Instead of analyzing the historical conditions under which the
object has assumed an even more global and powerful subjectivity, while
the vast majority of people have been reduced to the "bare life" of
objects, the products of social labor (and not the labor that produces
them) take the center stage of left theory. Having erased the labor that
produces the material world, by the same logic, the new materialism
assigns objects and matter an independent, self-transforming agency, or
an "inherent exuberance" (Coole 99). What is really an index of
profound social alienation resulting from private property relations is
turned upside down by the new materialists into a magical sign of the
"vitality" of matter and the natural world in which "these things, far
from being under [workers'] control, in fact control them" (Marx Capital, 167-68). To put this another way, the new de-centered
subject of posthumanist ontology—for whom matter emerges as the site of
uncontrollable, unknowable contingency—is the subject of austerity who
is expected to bow down to the dictates of capital. It is the insecure
subject for whom there will be no social security, the subject for whom
daily life is increasingly unpredictable, subject to chance, to the
market. Which is to say that the posthumanist ontology imports into
"matter" the irrational, apparently lawless dynamics of human life under
a global market and then re-situates this market logic as the post-logic
of nature and matter itself. This is the double-move by which the new
materialists foster the illusion of the inevitability of the world as it
is.
In this way, the new materialist ideology obscures the fact that, the
more capitalist relations "settle everywhere" around the world, the more
socialized production becomes, the more the material foundations are
laid for socialism, the wresting of freedom from necessity by the
revolutionary collective. Behind the turn to "matter" is the corporate
need to divert attention from the growing contradictions between the
socialized forces of production—which make it possible to feed, clothe,
educate, and provide healthcare for all—and the property relations that
ensure social production is privatized in the interests of the few.
While the right-wing of capital produces a vehemently anti-government
subject who sees ethics as a ruse of the federal government to give
"entitlements" to the "other" and who rejects social programs as
"handouts," the new materialist subject is the "caring" left-wing
subject of capital for whom ethics paves the way to a "fairer"
capitalism (Obama's "compromise" capitalism in which both the rich and
the poor are expected to "pay their fair share" to bail out big business
and save capitalism). In contrast to the "Say No to Sharing" ethos of
reactionary conservatives (aptly captured in Sprint’s commercial of the
same title), new materialism essentially offers a more complex version
of the corporate argument that, as a Starbucks commercial puts it, our
"community would be a better place" "if we cared all of the time the way
we care some of the time" (If You Vote"). "Fairness" is the banner of
those seeking not to end the relations that produce unfairness, but to
continue exploitation on less egregious ("inhumane") terms. Its main
goal is to disappear the system of capital that produces a widening gap
between exploited and exploiter. But it doesn't just try to convince
workers that they should be exploited even more. It insists that they
should find it "in themselves" to willingly demand such exploitation as
a sign of their ethical commitments—even in the face of brutal cuts to
the services they rely on to survive by their caring bosses. "Fairness"
is a cover for making the workers pay for the crisis.
To put this another way, while right wing discourse
normalizes the heightened competition of capital's private property
relations, the new materialism translates the increased socialization of
productive forces under capitalism into a "vibrant" force of matter
itself ("thing-power") so as to assert the force of "weak thinking"
(Vattimo) and the messianic vision of the Left which says goodbye to the
working class as the agent of change. It thereby naturalizes
(de-historicizes) production, rendering impossible the collective
transformation of private property relations that is necessary for
freedom from necessity. New materialists like Jane Bennett admit as
much. Speaking of the new materialist approach to matter, she writes,
Such a newfound attentiveness to matter and its
powers will not solve the problem of human exploitation or oppression,
but it can inspire a greater sense of the extent to which all bodies are
kin in the sense of inextricably enmeshed in a dense network of
relations. And in a knotted world of vibrant matter, to harm one section
of the web may very well be to harm oneself. Such an enlightened or
expanded notion of self-interest
is good for humans. (Bennett
Vibrant Matter 13)
New materialism acknowledges that it has little influence (let alone
interest) in addressing "exploitation and oppression" and in fact it
substitutes for this political project a new ethics of equality through
"feeling." But in the name of feeling it in fact manufactures the
illusion that a worker's "harming" of one section of the "web" by, for
instance, being inattentive to the contingent assemblages of "debris" in
a gutter, eating factory-farmed meat, not recycling, or polluting a
river with waste water are ultimately the same as a corporation's theft
of surplus value, decision to fire workers, cut their benefits, or
pollute the environment. It would be more precise to say that this
"newfound attentiveness to matter and its powers" is "good" for the
specific class interests of the human owners of capital. New materialism
is good for the bourgeoisie because it perpetuates the (green) class
mythology that "we are all in this together," when in fact class
relations ensure that all the sacrifices in support of the common "web"
come from the property-less, who have been reduced to the status of
things. One can look to what the appointed Emergency Manager of Detroit
is proposing to see the new forms in which brutal de-humanization of
working people manifests.
Both the right and left subjects of capital, in short, obscure the
foundation of the social in labor and production. But, trained to see
herself "enmeshed" in multiple "interlocking systems" in which all
people, regardless of class, are implicated, and (still) seduced by the culturalist claim that there is no longer any "outside" from which to
wage a struggle to end capitalism,
the feeling-green left subject is a more effective subject for
the advanced sectors of (transnational) capital. It is attentive to the
(unavoidable) interconnectedness of production and consumption, rich and
poor, the human and the nonhuman worlds. Yet precisely on this basis it
refuses the "binary" thinking and explanatory knowledges that make it
possible to understand (and thus transform) the class structures that
shape human life.
5.
As I have suggested, arguments that emphasize the hybrid nature of
subject-object relations are given pride of place in new materialist
analyses because they seem to embody a "postdualist ontology" (Coole
100). In her reading of Merleau-Ponty, for instance, Coole emphasizes
the concept of "fold" because it highlights, in Merleau-Ponty's words,
the "reflexivity of the sensible" whereby it becomes "impossible
to distinguish between what sees [or touches] and what is seen [or
touched]" (as qtd. in Coole 104). From within this ontological
framework, one cannot—and, as an ethical subject, should not—determine
where nature ends and where the human begins. Ethics is attentive to
this very indeterminacy.
However, it is precisely in such arguments that one can begin to discern
more clearly the philosophical revisionism that underwrites the new
materialist ontology and that ends up turning materialism into
aesthetics.
Acknowledging a difference between the subject and object (of knowledge)
is in fact central not just to humanism but to materialism. It is even a
basic (practical) understanding in the natural sciences and the
traditions of science the new materialists claim to support (e.g.,
Einstein, the new biology, nanotech). In the philosophical tradition of
materialism, one of the central questions is: does the world exist independently of the subject and its
consciousness, or is the world the product of consciousness—either of
the individual (in the case of subjective idealism) or of Spirit, God,
etc. (in the case of objective idealism)? In
Materialism and Empirio-Criticism,
Lenin's exhaustive critique of the "new materialists" of his day who
attempted to revise materialism into a new subjective idealism, Lenin
explains that "Matter is a philosophical category denoting the objective
reality which is given to man by his sensations, and which is copied,
photographed and reflected by our sensations, while existing
independently of them" (127). Here he emphasizes two important issues.
First, for materialism, the world exists independently of the subject
and is therefore independent—different—from it. It exists with or
without the (human) subject. Second, and at the same time, this does not
mean that the subject and object are fundamentally separate, for the
material world is "reflected" in the sensations and mind of the subject.
This is the case because the human subject is a dialectical product of
nature. It has evolved through the practice of labor. Marx in fact calls
this the "metabolic" relation of nature and labor. As Lenin shows, "in
order really to know an object we must embrace, study, all its sides,
all connections and 'mediations." Therefore, "the whole of human
experience should enter the full 'definition' of an object as a
criterion of the truth and as a practical index of the object's
connection with what man requires" (116-17). This is another way of
saying that for Lenin, "reflection" is a labor process. It is through
the generations of human labor that humans conceptualize the world
around them. Both in the sense that, through the dialectical relation of
nature and labor, humans create tools and products by which humans meet
their needs, and in the sense that the intellectual labor of
conceptualization itself depends upon human production. Through these
productive practices of labor, under definite social relations, humans
have evolved to be able to understand nature in increasingly complex
ways. And, as Lenin argues, conceptual, abstract knowledges that go
beyond feeling and experience are necessary because "abstraction
reflects nature more deeply, truly and completely" (Collected
Works vol. 38, 171).
The new materialists accept the first aspect of the basic idea of
matter—that it denotes an objective existence—but formally reject the
second aspect—that it is "reflected" in the human subject, or that the
subject's ideas "correspond" at an abstract level to the objective
world. "[T]he illusion of representational correspondence," as Coole
puts it in her annotation of Merleau-Ponty's critique of materialism, is
"sheer mysticism" (100). But, as Lenin argues, "Acceptance or rejection
of the concept matter is a question of the confidence man places in the
evidence of his sense-organs, a question of the source of our knowledge,
a question which has been asked and debated from the very inception of
philosophy" (Lenin 128). New materialists are quite confident that
matter exists independently of the subject, but, following the
textualist critique of representation, they oppose the idea that the
material world is "reflected" in the human subject and they are quick to
reject the slightest suggestion that humans have the capacity to
reliably know the world, or to comprehend it as a totality. Which is
another way of saying that, despite their criticisms of "dualist"
ontology, posthumanist theory in effect establishes a fundamental
(unbridgeable) gap between the subject and the object that prevents the
subject from conceptually understanding the material world. Like the
Feuerbachian and Berkeleian speculative materialism that claimed that,
while matter exists, the concepts we use to understand it, like order
and causality, are only imposed on nature by humans, the new
materialists are only "confident" in the sensory experiences of the
objective world, and only insofar as their senses affirm (their belief
in) the fundamental contingency of the world. Which is why Lenin calls
this (experiential) theory of knowledge "fideism" ("faith based"
religious obscurantism). It is not therefore a coincidence that new
materialists de-center human knowledge, only to re-center human
"ethics," which reflects the belief that how humans "feel" (belief,
desire, values, etc.) is more important than understanding things as
they are in reality. Concepts, new materialists suggest, do not—indeed
cannot—reflect objective aspects of matter itself.
It is significant in this context that while new materialists distance
themselves from both the "mechanical" approach to matter and to Kant's
dualism (Coole 99), in the actual conclusions they draw they are
mechanistic Kantians. Kant of course argued that we cannot know the
world "in itself," we can only know its effects on the subject. Insofar
as the new materialists insist both on the existence of the objective
world and on its "non-appropriable" "vitality" and "contingency" they in
effect place the "cause" or origin of matter beyond the reach of human
understanding (concepts). But as Engels argues, "In mechanics the causes
of motion are taken as given and their origin is disregarded, only their
effects being taken into account" (Dialectics
55). Mechanical materialism, in other words, is not mechanical for
positing determination, as new materialists claim. Rather, it is precisely
for putting causality and determination
beyond human understanding
that certain modes of materialism are mechanical. From this standpoint,
far from moving beyond mechanical materialism, the new materialists in
fact update it. They banish from the material world a dogmatic Deity, a
divine first cause, only to import into the material world a spiritual
impulse. Instead of an orthodox (and discredited) religious approach,
the new materialists seek to
"rediscover" a "certain energy in the pulsation of existence" (Coole
92). Bennett likewise suggests, "This materialism, which eschews
the life-matter binary and does not believe in God or spiritual forces,
nevertheless also acknowledges the presence of an indeterminate
vitality—albeit one that resists
confinement to a stable hierarchy—in the world" (Bennett
"A Vitalist Stopover"
63). Bennett makes clear here that "vibrant matter" is "vibrant"
precisely because it is "indeterminate," because its immanent yet
unknowable "agency" exceeds humans' ability to understand its
determination(s), since the hierarchies, if they exist, are always
changing. The notion of the "contingent" "agency" of matter as the
"event" that is both constitutive of the human and beyond human
understanding is perhaps best described by Engels in his critique of
Georges Cuvier: "In place of a single divine creation, he put a whole
series of repeated acts of creation, making the miracle an essential
natural agent"; he was thus "revolutionary in phrase and reactionary in
substance" (Dialectics of Nature
10). Indeed, miraculous
materialism is an apt name for the new materialism outlined by Bennett,
Coole and Frost et al. And central to its "reactionary substance" is the
positing of experience as the only way to fully appreciate miraculous
matter. To experience matter, new materialists suggest, is to encounter
matter prior to cognition, which imposes "false" ways of thinking, like
conceptualizing matter as reflecting "hierarchies" of determination or
"history."
The fantasy of an unmediated experience of matter takes a particularly
cynical form in Coole's reading of Merleau-Ponty's phenomenology. On the
one hand, she shows that Merleau-Ponty embraces romantics like Shelling
for his effort to see the "exuberance" (99) of matter but is critical of
the way that this leads to an aesthetic intuitionalism, because it
assumes an "identification" between subject and object. In this way, she
distances herself and Merleau-Ponty from "romantic" "mysticism" (100).
On the other hand, Coole, following Merleau-Ponty, treats Cézanne's
impressionism not as an articulation of an historical modality of
conceptualizing the world, but as somehow grasping reality itself
without mediation. "Cézanne's painting suspends these [reifying
linguistic] habits of thought and reveals the basis of inhuman nature
upon which man has installed himself" (104). Cézanne's form of painting
is a historical development—an abstraction made possible under certain
social conditions in the West. But Merleau-Ponty and Coole isolate
impressionism from history and treat it as revealing "perception"
without abstraction. Having critiqued an
earlier form of romantic mysticism, Coole goes on to advance another.
Materialist dialectics of nature, as Engels and Lenin emphasize, seeks to
understand nature and the agency of (inanimate) matter in its full
complexity. However, rather than assume one does this in the absence of human
thinking/culture, it acknowledges that the only way to accurately
(comprehensively) understand nature is to develop scientific knowledge
of it—which is the result of hundreds of thousands of years of human
development (human's dialectical relation to nature). Thus when Coole
insists, with regard to Euclid, that "The challenge is to suspend this
[Euclid's] culturally fashioned perception in order to uncover the
'vertical' world of 'brute' or 'wild' perception as it emerges" (105),
she relapses back into mysticism and erases the profound role of Euclid
in arriving at contemporary scientific theories of nature. But there is
no Heisenberg or Merleau-Ponty without Descartes and Euclid, all of whom
became who they were, and advanced their ideas, at particular stages of
sociohistorical development.
If it did not signal such a profound step backward for cultural theory,
new materialism's rejection of Marxism for its "illusion" of
correspondence between thought and the material world, on the one hand,
and, on the other, new materialism's unabashed desire for "unfettered
communication with the world" (Coole 99)—i.e., for aesthetic experiences
in which it is "impossible to say that nature ends here and that man or
expression starts here" (Merleau-Ponty as qtd. in Coole 104)—would
simply be laughable. But, as I have suggested, this is a mark of the
compromise that the left has made with capital. It has adopted the
language of science only insofar as science affirms that the world
remains "rippled with hidden recesses, shadows and shade, secrets and
anonymity" (Coole 113) and abandons the scientific approach to the
social as mode of production. For all its appeal to science, the new
materialism is entrenched in a mystifying aestheticism.
Take, for instance, such new materialist
statements about capital as the following: "Whatever passes through these economic circuits is redistributed
to the material advantage of some rather than others, while entering
into systemic relations that outrun the comprehension or intentions of
individual actors" (Coole and Frost 30). When it comes to offering
cutting-edge explanation of contemporary capitalism, what Coole and
Frost's arguments instead reveal is that new materialism aims primarily
to observe the effects of "economic circuits"—the increasingly
unavoidable social inequalities erupting everywhere on the surfaces of
capitalist culture—while suggesting that the deeper-lying causes of
these effects are unknowable and "for the most part unpredictable" (29).
Instead of departing from mainstream economic mantras, such claims
repeat in a left idiom the defenses of the market put forward by such
figures as former Chairman of the Federal Reserve Alan Greenspan, who in
his testimony to the Congressional Oversight Committee for the role he
played in the 2008 credit crisis insisted that no one could have
predicted the "once-in-a-century credit tsunami" (Lanman and Matthews).
Kant, of course, in discussing the sublime,
insisted that one should look at the ocean, not in terms of its causal
dynamics but "as the poets do" (Critique
of Judgment). That is to say, without attempting to explain it or
understand it, but only in terms of how it strikes the senses, or how it
appears. The sublime is precisely what Greenspan appeals to when he
insists that the economic crisis, like a tsunami, could not have been
foreseen. In an exemplary aesthetic gesture, new materialism likewise
places the laws of both nature and the social beyond human comprehension
and, in effect, produces a subject attentive to inequality and
simultaneously convinced that any effort to understand its roots—to
grasp a particular instance of inequality in relation to the social
totality—will fail, since material reality inevitably "outrun[s] the
comprehension" of individuals (Coole and Frost 30). This is precisely
the subject needed by capital to look upon the unfolding economic
contradictions as instances of the Kantian sublime—and it is no accident
that new materialists like Bennett (The Enchantment of Modern Life;
Vibrant Matter) and Ian Bogost
(Alien Phenomenology), dismiss
critique as an unethical effort to find causal relations at work in the
material world and call instead for a return to "wonder," or the
re-enchantment of the material that celebrates ethical "openness" to
unpredictability and surprise as a more authentic approach to
materiality.
The aesthetic subject is the subject especially
needed in the era of what Naomi Klein calls "shock and awe" capitalism.
Today more than ever capital requires a subject whose attentiveness to
her senses keeps her diverted from the underlying structure that makes
possible the increasingly devastating attacks on social programs.
Capital needs a "gated" subject imprisoned in her own experience. To
intervene into capitalist relations one should not embrace the
experiences that lead one to conclude that reality is inherently
unpredictable and resistant to human knowledge and control. Far from
reflecting a more "authentic" (human-decentered) approach to reality,
this is the market-centered fantasy of a world without regulation. This
is, in other words, the "non-human" world refracted through the very
property relations that continue to put human and natural life at risk.
Not only does this fantasy disappear the deeper-lying relations that
structure human experience; the focus on aesthetics of social and
natural life also cultivates new consumer subjects who are more inclined
to change lifestyle habits and patterns of thinking in line with new
green industries but who see anything more than such local changes as
arrogant, if not totalitarian: as "feed[ing] human hubris and our
earth-destroying fantasies of conquest and consumption" (Bennett, Vibrant Matter ix). Instead of uncritically affirming the experience
of uncertainty, one should seek to unearth the social structures that
have made material life "indeterminate." They do not originate in some
mysterious, universal quality of "life itself" but in the historical
relations of human life.
I have suggested that at the core of the aesthetic approach is an
experientialism that locates the world of matter in the subject's
experience of the objective world, particularly at the level of the body
and corporality (because, again, new materialists claim this avoids the
dualism and hierarchy of the humanist subject). We are all "kin,"
Bennett argues, because we all have bodies. By doing so, however, new
materialists reject the materialist position that existence is the
outside of consciousness and instead inscribe it within experience (the
body), as Nietzsche taught. The new materialists thus end up with a
blurry romanticism in which the human subject and matter are joined in
an exuberant unity, a pan-matterism in which it is impossible to make
political priorities based on class consciousness and which installs an
activism motivated by the intensity of feeling. Feeling the world needs
to change and performing that change in the micro-spaces of the daily
becomes more important than knowing how and why it changes due to
struggles over global property relations.
Here, it is important to note Melissa Orlie's text "Impersonal Matter" since it goes even further in its denunciation of concepts and history. Orlie reads Nietzsche's will to power as an "impersonal" theory of
materialism that eschews the relation between subject and object and,
ultimately, substance. Thus her text shows how new materialism brings
with it a whole romantic matrix of assumptions in the name of a view of
nature "free from culture" and especially the "rigidities" of thought.
More specifically, Orlie re-reads Nietzsche to put forward a new
objective idealism. "Will to power," she argues, is "an impersonal force
within our lives rather than as a personal one that is the property of
individuals" (118). On this basis, "what is conveniently called a self
is actually a complex of competing drives" (119). For Nietzsche, "mind is body" and thus mind is a
"trajectory of matter" (120, 121).
Tellingly, however, she does not explain
why we "remain attached to a sovereign conception of subjectivity"
(120) except by insisting that we are "positively averse to the
experience of impersonality" (120)—which is to repeat precisely what
needs to be explained. The implication is that we are just "naturally"
opposed to the way we "naturally" are. But this itself is contradictory.
It raises the question of why humans became "averse" to the way they
naturally are! The essay
skips answering this and instead argues that when confronted with the
real fact of impersonal matter we cannot control, we spontaneously
create "fantasies" of sovereignty and mastery (121).
Ultimately, Orlie's essay makes very clear that what is at stake is
deeper, affirmative experience of what already exists. She suggests that
to be "strong" willed is really to accept and immerse oneself in all
experience (123-5)—including suffering. At the same time, having a
strong will is "not to will"—to "suspend decision" (130). Which is
another way of celebrating "regression" (132) to a "sublimated" state of
"differentiated unity" which fosters creativity (132-3). This emphasis
is of course very similar to Cheah's and Derrida's celebration of
"passivity," not to mention Gianni Vattimo's "weak marxism" (see, for instance, Ecce Comu and his Hermeneutic Communism,
co-written with Santiago Zabala) and Agamben on "potentiality" (Potentialities:
Collected Essays in Philosophy).
William E. Connolly's contribution to New
Materialisms ("Materialities of Experience")
is also significant in this context—namely, its defense of
popular culture (Six Feet Under,
Waking Life) for its
depictions of "action suspended experience" (194) that, as in
Merleau-Ponty, helps overcome "resentment" and cultivates a "positive
existential attachment" (195) to others. The valorization of the weak is
part of the same conceptual move undertaken by Hardt and Negri to
establish "love" as the heart of the commons. It is no wonder that for
new materialists the "oppositional ways of thinking" associated with
"critique" (Coole and Frost 8) must give way to "affirmation" and
"positive" thinking (108) as the mark of radicality today.
6.
If the older forms of culturalism (e.g., Derrida, Butler, Hall, etc.)
treated matter in terms of language and cultural inscription (what new
materialists call "constructivism"), new materialism re-articulates
matter in terms of the natural sciences, especially the matter of
biology and physics. Both the old and "new" appeals to matter however
erase the historical foundation of matter, and put in its place the
"matter" of such things as language, the body, cells, particles, light
waves, which are all read as resistant to conceptual thought and
history-defying. Thus Coole and Frost emphasize that "On entering the
realm of subatomic particles one finds an even more quixotic and elusive
sense of matter" (Coole and Frost 11). As with the earlier
textual/cultural materialism, "matter" here is equated not so much with
the philosophical tradition of materialism for which matter has an
objective existence independent of the consciousness of the (human)
individual, but as that which resists individual comprehension/control.
Matter, on these terms, subverts human agency. This is particularly
evident in the posthumanist obsession with disaster and what Coole and
Frost call the "mismatches" between human intention and practice (16).
Such treatment of matter is one-sided in its privileging of what science
may not know (now). That is to say, it fetishizes the existing limits of
science, which are understood in local, culturalist terms (the God of
the gaps apologetics, again).
New materialism places under erasure the historical limits of science
that are themselves rooted in the mode of production. It consequently
leaves out the social conditions in which such things as language, the
body, and subatomic particles become meaningful.
In his critique of the natural sciences, Marx draws attention to this
tendency in science to abstract the object of analysis from history. The
"weaknesses of the abstract materialism of natural science" stem from
the fact that it is "a materialism which excludes the historical
process" (Capital 494, note
4). Excluding the historical relations of technology, for instance,
means ignoring that "[t]echnology reveals the active relation of man to
nature, the direct process of the production of his life, and thereby it
also lays bare the process of the production of the social relations of
his life and of the mental conceptions that flow from those relations" (Capital 493, note 4). Like technology, science reveals the relation
of humans to nature, "the direct process of the production of [human]
life and of the mental conceptions that flow from those relations." Not
only are the tools of science produced by labor (under specific class
conditions) but the very ability to recognize particular objects and
dynamics presupposes a certain stage of development (not just the
discourses that Foucault identified, but the structure of labor
relations that make scientific discourses possible and that shape the
form they take).
To leave out the class relations in which subatomic particles, light
waves and microbes, for instance, are (now) conceived of as the basis of
the material world not only occludes the exploited labor on which
scientific discovery depends under capitalism and bypasses the question
of why scientific advances are largely put out of reach of the vast
majority of humanity. Leaving out the historical conditions of matter
also reifies what Teresa Ebert and Mas'ud Zavarzadeh call the "local
modalities of matter." Matter, as they explain in Class in Culture,
is not a sign or any other physical body, nor is it the self-alienated
spirit or an intervention to support atheism (George Berkeley). To
identify matter with an object, an indivisible atom or any immutable
substance/motion, or to equate it with a quanta of light,
zero-dimensional point particles, or one-dimensional "strings"
("superstring theory"), is to make the local modalities of matter
absolute and to yield to the urge for physicalism and its metaphysical
twin (unchanging substance), in bourgeois philosophy and its ontology
and epistemology. Matter is objective reality in history—materialism; it
is not corporeality—matterism. (41)
The new materialists absolutize the "local modalities of matter" (41) by
treating matter as an object. As a consequence, they foster the
physicalism that isolates (reifies) objects from the relations which
make them possible.
Inquiry into the micro-levels of matter should not become an excuse for
theoretical myopia. New developments in biology and genetics are leading
to many important new advances, but they are shaped by the
contradictions of capitalism. Recent research on the human microbiome is
a case in point. The microbiome is the "resident community of microbes"
in and outside the human body "helping us to digest food, strengthen our
immune systems, and keep dangerous enemy pathogens from invading our
tissues and organs" (Mueller et al. 1246). Microbes (including for instance bacteria and viruses)
represent trillions of cells living in the human body and they are
increasingly being found to play important roles not just in keeping
people healthy but in causing or contributing to illness when imbalances
occur in the microbiome. Because the microbiome is being potentially
linked to such diseases/disorders as cancer, obesity, autism,
inflammatory bowel disease, and asthma, further study has the potential
to lead to new, integrative understandings of a wide range of diseases
and thus also new treatments that can help improve the lives of hundreds
of millions of people. In the process, it is certainly the case that
older ways of thinking about many other concepts will be undone to
develop better, more precise understandings, and new concepts will
emerged to analyze new dimensions of biological matter. In this regard,
a 2008 Nature editorial, in
commenting on the microbiome of the human gut, suggests that microbes
"contribute so much to human biology that it is difficult to say where
the body ends and the microbes begin — which is why several massive
projects have now started up to characterize the human microbiota in its
entirety" ("Who Are We?" 563). One example is The Human Microbiome
Project, starting in 2007, was "a 5-year, US$115-million effort to study
the microbial communities inhabiting several regions of the human body .
. . and how those communities influence human health and disease" ("The
Human Environment" 689). In fact, studies of the microbiome point to the
need for more "ecological" approaches to the understanding of the body,
to understand more comprehensively how systems within the body work
together (Mueller et al. 1246).
But under capitalism, these developments are driven by the relations of
profit and the results will be commodified. And today this
commodification takes place on an ever larger scale, as capital's
commodity relations become ever more generalized worldwide and the
social welfare states are under devistating attack, leading to the
privatization of formally nationalized healthcare systems. Privatization
is so normalized in mainstream culture in fact that the recent Supreme
Court ruling preventing the patenting of human genes was reported by
media primarily in terms of what this will mean for private companies
and corporate profits (Pollack).
Proponents of new biology, biotech, nanotech,... should be defending
the need for social science,
which is to say people's science. They should aggressively support new
developments in science not because they establish the aesthetic
qualities of matter, but because they are made possible by social
resources that all people should benefit from. Cultural theory should
resist the myopia that legitimates the market and instead boldly seek to
relate discoveries and their implications to the social totality. It
should re-claim the social basis of privatized science and defend the
need for totalizing knowledges that can help guide radical praxis to
bring about a world in which people's needs, not profit, shape the
priorities of science and medicine.
However the approach taken by new materialists instead more or less
mirrors defenders of corporate science, because its focus is on the
positive possibilities such developments reflect abstracted from the
class relations which necessarily limit science to the dictates of
profit.
This becomes clearer upon examining the way an
Economist cover story on the microbiome represents new developments.
Titled "Microbes Maketh Man," the article heralds the scientific
"revolutionaries" who are currently turning the world "inside out" in
their study of "what, biologically speaking, a human being is" (9). It
notes that while traditional (genetic) thinking about the human body has
viewed it as "a collection of 10 trillion cells which are themselves the
products of 23,000 genes," the "revolutionaries" argue that "in the
nooks and crannies of every human being, and especially in his or her
guts, dwells the microbiome: 100 trillion bacteria of several hundred
species bearing 3m non-human genes" (9). And, following the wider
posthumanist de-centering of the human, the article highlights the role
of the (micro) organisms (in this case "bugs" that regulate the human
body and thus protect it) on which humans depend. Under a subheading
titled "All In This Together," the article articulates a similarly
indeterminate view of the human and the nonhuman found in posthumanist
theory, emphasizing that "the bugs are neither parasites nor passengers.
They are, rather, fully paid-up members of a community" (9) of the human
host, which is no longer thought of as an "individual" but an
"ecosystem." The article emphasizes the increasing "popularity" of this
new scientific view of the human.
However, the "popular" narratives—which are largely structured by
posthumanist assumptions—omit that this re-understanding of the human
body represents a new advance made possible by labor, within the
exploitative structure of wage-labor. Such an omission of course also
erases the fact that under different social relations of production,
such scientific advances could be used, not to produce profit but to
advance human well-being. Popular narratives take for granted that under
capitalism such medical treatments will be accessible only to those who
can afford them. What makes posthumanist and new materialist theories so
popular in fact is that, in the language of "nature" ("biology"), they
smooth out the material contradictions of daily life, promote a flexible
new notion of the human subject of labor, and create a friction-free
cultural imaginary necessary to capital. That is, a world in which all
former boundaries breakdown: an inverted world which appears as a
constantly changing web of interconnections which we're "all in
together" but which is in fact constantly being "re-made" to accumulate
more surplus value from workers in more flexible ways, no matter the
human or environmental consequences.
What makes new materialism so resonant with the language of
The Economist is that both
articulate, more or less overtly, corporate science: the commitment to
profit from science by producing market based solutions at a price
rather than finding solutions that benefit all by connecting science to
the historic struggle to end private property relations. As is
highlighted by The Economist, new discoveries
related to the microbiome point to such "promising" new directions in
medicine as "more sophisticated deployment of the humble antibiotic,
arguably the pharma industry's most effective invention" (9). It is
important to note in this context that the Human Microbiome Project,
spearheaded by the National Institutes of Health and a consortium of
other researchers, that led to the new discoveries discussed by The Economist and in many other popular culture and theoretical
venues, is being backed by powerful "biocapitalists" like Craig J.
Venter and the pharmaceutical industry. Just as significant,
"bioinformatics" and the production of new technologies to store and
analyze the immense amount of meta-data being accumulated by the project
are leading to new DNA-sequencing technologies. As one report put it,
there is a "race to sequence DNA faster and more cheaply" (Blow 687).
This of course is deeply tied to the booming data collecting technology
industry, which provides technologies not only for medicine and science
but "national security."
Increasingly popular discussion of new levels of matter, like the
microbiome, reflects these new developments at the level of the
productive forces. Yet, perhaps most telling about The Economist is the way it has to
admit that these developments will remain fettered by private
property relations, and that, in fact, these developments
will be used as band-aids because they are profitable and avoid
structural changes needed to address underlying social causes of
illness. In "The Human Microbiome," a further development of its lead
article, The Economist goes on
to represent the study of the microbiome as leading to a potential means
of curing malnutrition in the developing world—as if malnutrition
was not rooted in the social relations of exploitation but the
individual's community of microbes. While the article cannot possibly
not reference as a factor the "cultural" issues (72) that are involved
in malnutrition (and here again "cultural" is the term under which
economic relations disappear), the effect of the article is to focus on
world hunger as a "microbial" matter and the way in which privatized
medicine will be able to profit from dealing with it in this manner.
Like new materialism, the article makes the global social relations of
capitalism one of numerous factors that indeterminately contribute to
the way things are, so that the way things are appear too "overwhelming"
to be addressed except in local terms that never address the capitalist
system itself. The privatization of science cannot produce what the hype
promises because of its failure to address the underlying causes of
health, for example, which lie in the existing class arrangements.
Driven by advances in productive forces in the 21st century, the "matter"
of "nature" has become one of the most effective grounds of naturalizing
capitalism. Having been re-read in cultural terms as excessive (just as
textuality had been), nature is more encompassing—indeed
"totalizing"—than textuality or culture, for it extends beyond the
"human" world to include nonhuman life. The irony, of course, is that
far from reflecting an ethics that de-centers the role of the human,
posthumanism and new materialism reflect an even more totalizing
colonization of the cultural turn, projecting the romantic culturalist
clichés of indeterminacy onto all of human and nonhuman life. This shows
that it is not "human" projections (abstract concepts) onto nature that
are the real issue; the issue is which abstractions are deemed
legitimate and thus win the title of "truthful" and "authentic"
("natural") representations of nature. And what counts as "truthful"
under capitalism is never primarily a matter of ideas but rather the
class interests ideas serve.
7.
In her defense of vitalists like Bergson and Driesch, Bennett tellingly
acknowledges that they "perhaps [...] enjoyed popularity in America [...]
because [they were] received as [...] defender[s] of freedom, of a
certain open-endedness to life, in the face of a modern science whose
pragmatic successes were threatening to confirm definitively the picture
of the universe as a godless machine" ("A Vitalist Stopover" 49;
my emphasis). But this romantic notion of freedom is
exactly what makes the new materialism itself so popular with publishers
and in universities today. Following posthumanist theory, it is largely
received as a "defender of freedom" from instrumentality.
With the corporatization of the universities, which has meant the
erosion and marketization of the humanities on the one hand and enormous
corporate funding of the sciences on the other, scholars in the
humanities are increasingly put under pressure to defend their role in
the market. New materialism is one of the ways in which theorists are
helping to make the humanities "relevant" by both drawing on new
developments in sciences (biogenetics, nanotech, the "new biology,"
etc.) and by doing this in such a way that the fundamental philosophical
questions get blurred over or do not get raised. It thereby provides
critics of capitalist life with the "semblance of an agreement with the
latest findings of the natural sciences" (Lukács 27) while at the same time ensuring that science is not used to
develop understanding of the material interconnections of social life
but to reconcile people to the ways in which the world will forever be
"rippled with hidden recesses" and "shadows" that defy human
calculation. In this way, theorists help to keep the humanities a place
where speculative knowledge not only reigns but has clear tie-ins to the
corporate sciences (which are violently opposed to dialectics and
steeped in positivism). In fact, centers like Arizona State's Global
Institute of Sustainability and Tom Cohen's Institute for Critical
Climate Change at SUNY-Albany, which like new materialism are part of
the "posthumanities," are among the few places where funding is
available for the development of the humanities—not so much because they
are "interdisciplinary" but because they are marketable. New materialism
opens up a new market for cultural theory. It cultivates an
entrepreneurial ethos in its emphasis on contingency and non-totalizable
difference: the "valorization of freedom or the element of
unpredictability and indeterminacy in action" (Bennett 61).
But, as Engels argues, "Freedom does not consist in the dream of
independence of natural laws, but in the knowledge of these laws, and in
the possibility this gives of systematically making them work toward
definite ends" (Anti-Dühring 125). By updating rather than fighting spiritualism, new materialism
ends up taking the side of the free market in the great struggle over
ownership of social resources. Its growing popularity needs to be
understood not as a result of its more "realist" approach but its
radical rearguardism that offers subjects "the semblance of total
freedom, the illusion of personal autonomy…while maintaining an attitude
that continually links them with the reactionary bourgeoisie in their
real dealings and renders them absolutely subservient to it" (Lukács
22-3).
Works Cited
Agamben, Giorgio, and Daniel Heller-Roazen. Potentialities: Collected Essays
in Philosophy. Stanford, CA: Stanford University Press, 1999. Print.
Ahmed, Sara. "Orientations Matter." Coole and Frost 234-257.
Bennett, Jane. The Enchantment of
Modern Life: Attachments, Crossings, and Ethics. Princeton, N.J.:
Princeton University Press, 2001. Print.
---. Vibrant Matter: A Political
Ecology of Things. Durham, N.C.: Duke University Press, 2010. Print.
---. "A Vitalist Stopover on the Way to a New Materialism." Coole and
Frost 47-69.
Blow, Nathan. "Exploring Unseen Communities."
Nature 453 (29 May 2008): 687-690. Print.
Bogost, Ian. Alien Phenomenology, or, What It's Like to Be a Thing. Minneapolis:
University of Minnesota Press. Print.
Cheah, Pheng. "Non-Dialectical
Materialism." Coole and Frost 70-91.
Connolly, William E. "Materialities of Experience." Coole and Frost 178-200.
Coole, Diana and Samantha Frost, eds. New Materialisms: Ontology,
Agency, and Politics. Durham and London: Duke UP, 2010. Print.
Coole, Diana. "The Inertia of Matter and the Generativity of Flesh." Coole and Frost 92-115.
Derrida, Jacques. Specters of
Marx: The State of the Debt, the Work of Mourning and the New International. Trans. Peggy Kamuf. New York and London:
Routledge, 2006. Print.
---. Of Grammatology. Trans.
Gayatri Spivak. Baltimore: Johns Hopkins University Press, 1978. Print.
---. and Alan Bass, and Henri Ronse. Positions. Chicago: University
of Chicago Press, 1981. Print.
Ebert, Teresa L., and Mas ud Zavarzadeh. Class in Culture. Boulder,
Colo.: Paradigm Publishers, 2008. Print.
Engels, Frederick. Dialectics of
Nature. Trans. Clemens Dutt. New York: International Publishers, 1940. Print.
---. Anti-Dühring: Herr Eugen
Dühring's Revolution in Science. New York: International Publishers,
1972. Print.
Frost, Samantha. "Fear and the Illusion of Autonomy." Coole and Frost 158-177.
Hardt, Michael, and Antonio Negri. Commonwealth. Cambridge, MA.: Belknap Press of Harvard University Press, 2009. Print.
Hall, Gary. Culture in Bits: The
Monstrous Future of Theory. New York: Continuum, 2002. Print.
"The Human Environment," Nature
453 (29 May 2008): 689.
Print.
"The Human Microbiome: Me, Myself, Us." The Economist. 18-24 August
2012: 69-72. Print.
Kant, Immanuel, and Werner S. Pluhar. Critique of Judgment.
Indianapolis: Hackett Pub. Co., 1987. Print.
Klein, Naomi.
The Shock Doctrine: The Rise of Disaster Capitalism. New York:
Picador, 2008. Print.
Lanman, Scott and Steve Matthews. "Greenspan Concedes to ‘Flaw’ in His
Market Ideology (Update2)." Bloomberg.com 23 Oct. 2008. Web. 5 October
2013.
Lenin.V.I. Materialism and Empirio-Criticism. Moscow: Foreign Languages Publishing House.
Print.
---. Conspectus of Hegel's
Science of Logic.
Collected Works Vol 38. Moscow: Progress Publishers, 1972. 85-238.
Print.
Lukács, Georg. Destruction of Reason. London: Merlin Press, 1980. Print.
Marx, Karl.
Critique of the Gotha
Programme. The Marx-Engels
Reader. Ed. Robert C.
Tucker. New York: W. W.
Norton & Company, 1978.525-41. Print.
Marx, Karl.
Capital. Vol. I. Trans. B. Fowkes. New York: Penguin, 1977. Print.
"Microbes Maketh Man." The
Economist. 18-24 August 2012: 9. Print.
Mueller, Kristen, Caroline Ash, Elizabeth Pennisi, and Orla Smith. "The
Gut Microbiota." Introduction to
Special Issue. Science Vol 336
(8 June 2012): 1246. Print. Nietzsche, Frederick. "On Truth and Lie in an Extra-Moral
Sense." The Portable
Nietzsche
Reader. Ed. Walter Kauffman. New York: Penguin Books, 1984. 42-47. Print.
Orlie, Melissa A. "Impersonal Matter." Coole and Frost 116-136.
Poe. Andrew. "Things-Beyond-Objects." Rev of
New Materialisms: Ontology, Agency, and Politics, eds. Diana Coole and Samantha Frost.
Journal of French and Francophone Philosophy. Vol XIX, No 1. (2011) 153-164. Print.
Pollack,
Andrew. "After Patent Ruling, Availability of Gene Tests Could Broaden."
New York Times. 13 June 2013. Web. 12 Sept 2013.
Sprint.
"Say No to Sharing-Family Meeting." Advertisement. September 2012.
Television.
Starbucks. "If You Vote, Starbucks Buys Your Coffee." Advertisement. 4
Nov. 2008.Television.
Scannell, Kara and Sudeep Reddy. "Greenspan
Admits Errors to Hostile House Panel." Wall Street Journal.
WSJ.com. 24 Oct. 2008. Web. 29
June 2013.
Vattimo, Gianni, and Santiago Zabala. Hermeneutic Communism: From
Heidegger to Marx. New York: Columbia University Press, 2011. Print.
Vattimo, Gianni, Pier Aldo Rovatti, and Peter Carravetta, eds.
Weak Thought. Albany: State University of New York Press, 2013.
Print.
"Who Are We?" Editorial. Science
453.7195 (29 May 2008): 563. Print. |
|